18

Joel Bruneau and Clinton Mahoney

Learning Objectives

  • Describe game theory and they types of situations it describes
  • Describe normal form games and identify optimal strategies and equilibrium outcomes in such games
  • Describe sequential move games and explain how they are solved
  • Describe repeated games and the difference between finitely repeated game and infinitely repeated games and their equilibrium

Module 18: Game Theory

Policy Example: Do We Need to Regulate Banks to Save Them From Themselves?

In the real estate and banking crisis that caused the United States to fall into the worst recession since the Great Depression, banks were seen to have engaged in reckless and risky behavior that was seemingly against their self-interest. Part of the risky behavior was attributed to the relaxation of banking regulations, particularly those that separated commercial banks from investment banks. But the question of why banks would engage in self-destructive behavior in the first place is one that puzzles many observers who have a background in economics and knows that free markets often direct individual self-interested action toward the good of society.

One possible explanation for this disconnect is the possibility that the banking industry is much more strategic than policy makers understood. The strategic incentives to take risks could be a lot more powerful then generally appreciated. The nature of this strategic environment and the incentives it provides are essential to understand to be able to make appropriate and effective policy.

Exploring the Policy Question

  1. What are the strategic incentives for banks to take risks?
  2. What policy solutions present themselves from this analysis?

18.1 What is Game Theory?

Learning Objective 18.1: Describe game theory and they types of situations it describes.

18.2 Single Play Games

Learning Objective 18.2: Describe normal form games and identify optimal strategies and equilibrium outcomes in such games.

18.3 Sequential Games

Learning Objective 18.3: Describe sequential move games and explain how they are solved.

18.4 Repeated Games

Learning Objective 18.4: Describe repeated games and the difference between finitely repeated game and infinitely repeated games and their equilibrium.

 

 

18.1 What is Game Theory?

Learning Objective 18.1: Describe game theory and they types of situations it describes.

Until this module we have studied economic decision making in situations where an agent’s payoff is based on his, her or its actions alone. In other words the payoff to an agent’s actions is known and the trick is to figure out how to get the highest payoff. But there are many situations in which the payoffs to an agent’s actions are determined in part by the actions of other agents. Consider this simple example. On Saturday, you know there are a number of parties happening in and around your school. How much you will enjoy attending any one party is in large part determined by how many of your friends will be there. In other words, your payoff is a function not only of your decision about which party to attend but also a function of the decisions of your friends. We call these types of interactions strategic interactions, where agents must anticipate the actions of others when making decisions, and we use game theory to model them so that we can think about the outcomes of these interactions just like we think about outcomes in markets without strategic interaction like the price and quantity outcome in a product market. The study of these models is called game theory: the study of strategic interactions among economic agents.

Game theory is extremely useful because it allows us to anticipate the behavior of economic agents within a game and the outcomes of strategic games. Game theory gets its name from actual games. Games like checkers and chess are strategic games where two players interact and the outcome of the game is determined by the actions of both players. In economics, game theory is particularly useful in understanding imperfectly competitive markets like oligopoly – the subject of the next module – because the price and output decisions of one firm affects the demand and therefore profit function of the other firms. But before we can study oligopoly markets, we must first understand games and how to analyze them. In this module we will consider only non-cooperative games, games where the players are not able to negotiate and make binding agreements within the game. An example of a cooperative game might be one where two poker payers agree to share winnings no matter who actually wins, as a result their strategies are based on how best to maximize the joint expected payoff, not individual payoffs.

All games have three basic elements: players, strategies and payoffs. The players of the game are the agents actively participating in the game and who will experience outcomes based on the play of all players. The strategies are all of the possible strategic choices available to each player, they can be the same for all players or different for each player. The payoffs are the outcomes associated with every possible strategic combination, for each player. Any complete description of a game must include these three elements. In the games that we will study in this module, we will assume that each player’s goal is to maximize their individual payoff which is consistent with the rational utility-maximizing agent that is the foundation of modern economic theory.

We begin by separating games into two basic types: simultaneous games and sequential games. Simultaneous games are games in which players take strategic actions at the same time, without knowing what move the other has chosen. A good example of this type of game is the matching coins game where two players each have a coin and choose which side to face up. They then reveal their choices simultaneously and if they match one player gets to keep both coins and if they don’t match the other player keeps both coins. Sequential games are games where players take turns and move consecutively. Checkers, chess and go are all good examples of sequential games. One player observes the move of the other player, then makes their play and so on.

Games can also be single-shot or repeated. Single-shot games are played once and then the game is over. Repeated games are simultaneous move games played repeatedly by the same players. A single-shot game might be a game of rock, paper, scissors played once to determine who gets to sit in the front seat of a car. A repeated game might be repeated plays of rock, paper, scissors with the first player to win five times getting the right to sit in the front seat of a car.

Games can become very complicated when all players do not know all the information about the game. For the purposes of this module, we will assume common knowledge. Common knowledge is when the players know all about the game – the players, strategies and payoffs – and know that the other players know, and that the other players know that they know, and so on ad infinitum. In simpler terms all participants know everything.

18.2 Single Play Games

Learning Objective 18.2: Describe normal form games and identify optimal strategies and equilibrium outcomes in such games.

The most basic of games is the simultaneous, single play game. We can represent such a game with a payoff matrix: a table that lists the players of the game, their strategies and the payoffs associated with every possible strategy combination. We call games that can be represented with a payoff matrix, normal-form games.

Let’s start with an example of a game among two friends, Erika and Sven, who are competing to be the top student in a class. They have a final exam approaching and they are deciding whether they should be cooperative and share notes or be uncooperative and keep their notes to themselves. They won’t see each other at the end of the day so they each have to decide whether to leave notes for each other without knowing what the other one has done. If they both share notes they both will get perfect scores. Their teacher gives a ten point bonus to the top exam score, but only of there is one exam better than the rest so if they both get top score there is no bonus and they both get 100 on their exams. If they both don’t share they wont do as well and they will both receive a 95 on their exams. However if one shares and the other doesn’t the one who shares will not benefit from the other’s notes, so will only get a 90 and the one who doesn’t share will benefit from the other’s notes, get the top score and the bonus for a score of 110.


All of these facts are expressed in the payoff matrix in Figure 18.2.1. Since this is a single-shot, simultaneous game it is a normal-form game and we can use a payoff matrix to describe it. There are two players: Lena and Sven. There are two strategies available to each player. Lena’s strategies are in blue and correspond to the rows and Sven’s are in red and correspond to the columns and they are the same for both: share or don’t share. The payoffs for each strategy combination are given in the corresponding row and column and Lena’s payoffs are in blue and Sven’s payoffs are in red. We will assume common knowledge – they both know all of this information about the game, and they know that the other knows it, and they know that the other knows that they know it, and so on.

Figure 18.2.1: The Valedictorian Game

Sven

Share

Don’t Share

Lena

Share

100, 100

90, 110

Don’t Share

110, 90

95, 95

The payoff matrix a complete description of the game because it lists the three elements: players, strategies and payoffs.

It is now time to think about individual strategy choices. We will start by examining the difference between dominant and dominated strategies. A dominant strategy is a strategy for which the payoffs are always greater than any other strategy no matter what the opponent does. A dominated strategy is a strategy is a strategy for which the payoffs are always lower than any other strategy no matter what the opponent does. Predicting behavior in games is achieved by understanding each rational player’s optimal strategy, the one that leads to the highest payoff. Sometimes the optimal strategy depends on the opponent’s strategy choice, but in the case of a dominant strategy, it does not and so it follows that a rational player will always play a dominant strategy if one is available to them. It also follows that a rational player will never play a dominated strategy. So we now have our first two principles that can, in certain games, lead to a prediction about the outcome.

Let’s look at the Valedictorian Game in Figure 18.2.1. Notice that for Lena she gets a higher payoff if she doesn’t share her notes no matter what Sven does. If Sven shares his notes, she gets 110 if she doesn’t share rather than 100 if she does. If Sven doesn’t share his notes, she gets 95 if she doesn’t share and 90 if she does. It makes sense then that she will never share her notes. Don’t share is a dominant strategy so she will play it. Share is a dominated strategy so she will not play it. The same is true for Sven as the payoffs in this game happen to be completely symmetrical, though they need not be in games. We can predict that both players will choose to play their dominant strategies and that the outcome of the game will be don’t share, don’t share – Lena chooses don’t share and Sven chooses don’t share – and they both get 95.

This outcome is known as a Dominant Strategy Equilibrium (DSE), an equilibrium where each player plays his or her dominant strategy. This is a very intuitive equilibrium concept and is the one used in situations where all players have a dominant strategy. Unfortunately many, or even most, games do not have the feature that every player has a dominant strategy. Let’s examine the DSE in this game. The most striking feature of this outcome is that there is another outcome that both players would voluntarily switch to: share, share. This outcome delivers 100 to each player and is therefore more efficient in the Pareto sense – there is another outcome where you could make one person better off without hurting anyone else. Games with this feature are known as Prisoner’s Dilemma games – the name comes from a classic game of cops and robbers, but the general usage is for games that have this Pareto suboptimal feature.

Why do we get this suboptimal result? It comes from the fact that each agent is purely self-interested, all they care about is maximizing their own payoffs, and if they think the other player is going to play share, their best play is to not share. What is particularly interesting about this result is that it overturns the first welfare theorem of economics that says that a competitive equilibrium is Pareto Efficient. The difference is the strategic nature of the interactions in the game. Here we have much of the same conditions of a competitive market, but because of the strategic nature of the game, one player’s actions affects the other players’ payoffs.

What if a game lack dominant strategies? Let’s go back to the example of the last section where you are thinking about which party to attend because you want to meet up with friends. Let’s simplify the example by saying that there are two friends Malia and Caitlin who both have been invited to two parties, one sponsored by the college international club and another sponsored by the college debate club. Neither of them have a particular preference about which party they want to go to, but they definitely want to see each other and so want to end up at the same party. They talked earlier in the week and so they know that each is considering the two parties and how much each of them like the two parties, so there is common knowledge. The problem is that Caitlin’s mobile phone battery has run out of charge and they can’t communicate. When asked how much they would enjoy the parties Caitlin and Malia gave similar answers and we will represent them as payoffs in the payoff matrix in Figure 18.2.2.

Figure 18.2.2: The Party Game

Malia

International Club (IC)

Debate Club (DC)

Caitlin

International Club (IC)

10, 15

2, 1

Debate Club (DC)

1, 2

15, 10

This matrix shows Caitlin’s strategies on the left in a column and Malia’s strategies in a row on top. Each of them has exactly two strategies: International Club and Debate Club. Foe each their payoffs are shown in the boxes that correspond to each strategy pair. For example in the box for International Club, International Club the payoffs are 10 and 10. The first payoff corresponds to Caitlin and the second corresponds to Malia.

We now have to determine each players best response function: one player’s optimal strategy choice for every possible strategy choice of the other player. For Caitlin, her best response function is the following:

Play IC if Malia plays IC

Play DC if Malia plays DC

For Malia, her best response function looks similar:

Play IC if Caitlin plays IC

Play DC if Caitlin plays DC

Since the best response changes for both players depending on the strategy choice of the other player, we know immediately that neither one has a dominant strategy. What then? How do we think about the outcome of the game? The solution concept most commonly used in game theory is the Nash equilibrium concept. A Nash equilibrium is an outcome where, given the strategy choices of the other players, no individual player can obtain a higher payoff by altering their strategy choice. An equivalent way to think about Nash equilibrium is that it is an outcome of a game where all players are simultaneously playing a best response to the others’ strategy choices. The equilibrium is intuitive, if, when placed in a certain outcome, no player wishes to unilaterally deviate from it, then equilibrium is achieved – there are no forces within the game that would cause the outcome to change.

In the party game above, there are two outcomes where the best responses correspond: both players choosing IC and both players choosing DC. If Caitlin shows up at the International Club party and finds Malia there, she will not want to leave Malia there and go to the Debate Club party. Similarly if Malia shows up at the International Club party and finds Caitlin there, she will not want to leave Caitlin there and go to the Debate Club party. So the outcome (IC, IC) – which describes Caitlin’s choice and Malia’s choice is a Nash equilibrium. The outcome (DC, DC) is also a Nash equilibrium for the same reason.

This example illustrates the strengths and weaknesses of the Nash equilibrium concept. Intuitively, if they show up at the same party, both women would be content and neither one would want to leave to the other party if the other is staying. However, there is nothing in the Nash equilibrium concept that gives us guidance as to predicting at which party the women will end up. In general, a normal form game can have zero, one or multiple Nash equilibrium.

Consider this different version of the party game where Caitlin really doesn’t want to go to the International Club party, so much so that she prefers attending the Debate Club party without Malia to attending the International Club party with Malia.

Figure 18.2.3: The Party Game, Version 2

Malia

International Club (IC)

Debate Club (DC)

Caitlin

International Club (IC)

1, 15

2, 1

Debate Club (DC)

5, 2

15, 10

Now DC is a dominant strategy for Caitlin. Malia knows Caitlin does not like the International Club party and will correctly surmise that she will attend the Debate Club party no matter what. So both Caitlin and Malia will go to the Debate Club party and (DC, DC) is the only Nash Equilibrium. In this case the Nash equilibrium concept is satisfying, it gives a clear prediction of the unique outcome of the game and it intuitively makes sense.

Another possibility is a game that has no Nash equilibrium. Consider the following game called matching pennies. In this game two players, Ahmed and Naveen, each have a penny. They decide which side of the penny to have facing up and cover the penny until they are both revealed simultaneously. By agreement, if the pennies match Ahmed gets to keep both and if the two pennies don’t match, Naveen keeps both. The players, strategies, and payoffs are given in the payoff matrix in Figure 18.2.4.

Figure 18.2.4: The Matching Pennies Game

Naveen

Heads

Tails

Ahmed

Heads

1, -1

-1, 1

Tails

-1, 1

1, -1

Ahmed’s best response function is to play heads if Naveen plays heads and to play tails if Naveen plays tails. Naveen’s best response is to play tails if Ahmed plays heads and to play heads if Ahmed plays tails. As you can clearly see, there is no correspondence of best response functions, no outcome of the game in which no player would want to unilaterally deviate and thus no Nash equilibrium. The outcome of this game is unpredictable and no outcome creates contentment for both players.

Finding the Nash equilibrium in normal form games is made relatively easy by following a simple technique that identifies the best response functions on the payoff matrix itself. To do so, simply underline the maximum payoff for a given opponent strategy. Consider the example below. For Chris, if Pat plays Left, the maximum payoff is 65 which comes from playing Up, so let’s underline 65. This is a representation of the best response to Pat playing left, Chris should play Up. Moving along the columns we find that Chris should play Down if Pat plays Center, and Chris should play Down again if Pat plays Right. Switching perspective, if Chris plays Up Pat gets a maximum payoff from playing Left so we underline Pat’s payoff, 44, in that box. Continuing on, if Chris plays Middle, Pay should play Right, and if Chris plays Down, Pat should play Center.

Pat

Left

Center

Right

Chris

Up

65, 44

29, 38

44, 29

Middle

53, 41

35, 31

19, 56

Down

30, 57

41, 63

72, 27

So now that we have identified each players best response functions, all that remains is to look for outcomes where the best response functions correspond. Such outcomes are those where both payoffs are underlined. In this game the two Nash equilibria are (Up, Left) and (Down, Center).

NOTE ON DOMINANT STRATEGY AND NASH EQUILIBRIUM

If we change the payoffs in the game to what is shown below notice that each player has a dominant strategy as see by the thee underlines all in the row ‘Down’ for Chris and three underlines all in the column ‘Center’ for Pat. Down is always the best strategy choice for Chris no matter what Pat chooses and Center is always the right strategy choice for Pat no matter what Chris chooses.

Pat

Left

Center

Right

Chris

Up

30, 41

29, 44

44, 24

Middle

53, 33

35, 56

19, 39

Down

65, 57

41, 63

72, 27

Note also that the dominant strategy equilibrium (Down, Center) also fulfills the requirements of a Nash equilibrium. This will always be true of dominant strategy equilibria: all dominant strategy equilibria are Nash equilibria. From the example above, however, we know the reverse is not true: not all Nash equilibria are dominant strategy equilibria. So dominant strategy equilibria are a subset of Nash equilibria, or to put it in another way, the Nash equilibrium is a more general concept than Dominant Strategy Equilibrium.

Mixed Strategies

So far we have concentrated on pure strategies where a player chooses a particular strategy with complete certainty. We now turn our attention to mixed strategies where a player randomizes across strategies according to a set of probabilities he or she chooses. For an example of a mixed strategy let’s return to the matching pennies game in Figure 18.2.4.

Figure 18.2.4: The Matching Pennies Game

Naveen

Heads

Tails

Ahmed

Heads

1, -1

-1, 1

Tails

-1, 1

1, -1

As was noted before and as we can see by using the underline strategy to illustrate best responses, there is no Nash equilibrium of this game in pure strategies. What about mixed strategies? A mixed strategy is a strategy itself, for example Ahmed might decide that he will play heads 75% of the time and tails 25% of the time. What is Neveen’s best response to this strategy? Well if Naveen plays tails with certainty, he will win 75% of the time. Ahmed’s best response to Naveen playing tails is to play tails with certainty, so Ahmed’s mixed strategy is not a Nash equilibrium strategy. How about Ahmed choosing a mixed strategy of playing heads and tails each with a 50% chance – simply flipping the coin – can this be a Nash equilibrium strategy? The answer is yes which is evident when we think of Naveen’s best response to this mixed strategy. Naveen can play either heads or tails with certainty or the same mixed strategy with equal results, he can expect to win half the time. We know that the pure strategies have best responses as given in the matrix above so only the mixed strategy is a Nash equilibrium. If Ahmed decides to flip his coin, Naveen’s best response is to flip his too. And if Naveen is flipping his coin, Ahmed’s best response is to do the same.

So this game, that did not have a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies, does have a Nash equilibrium in mixed strategies. Both players randomize over their two strategy choices with probabilities .5 and .5.

18.3 Sequential Games

Learning Objective 18.3: Describe sequential move games and explain how they are solved.

There are many situations where players of a game move sequentially. The game of checkers is such a game, one player moves, the other players observes the move and then responds with their own move. Sequential move games are games where players take turns making their strategy choices and observe their opponents choice prior to making their own strategy choices. We describe these games by drawing a game tree, a diagram that describes the players, their turns, their choices at every turn, and the payoffs for every possible set of strategy choices. We have another name for this description of sequential games: extensive form games.

Consider a game where two Indian food carts located next to each other are competing for many of the same customers for its Tikka Masala. The first cart, called Ashok’s, opens first and sets its price, the second cart, called Tridip’s opens second and sets its price after observing the price set by Ashok’s. To keep it simple let’s suppose there are three prices possible for both carts: high, medium, low.

The extensive form, or game tree representation of this game is given in Figure 18.3.1. The game tree describes all of the principle elements of the game: the players, the strategies and the payoffs. The players are described at each decision node of the game, each place where a player might potentially have to choose a strategy. From each node there extend branches representing the strategy choices of a player. At the end of the final set of branches are the payoffs for every possible outcome of the game. This is the complete description of the game. There are also subgames within the full game. Subgames are the all of the subsequent strategy decisions that follow from one particular node.

Figure 18.3.1: The Curry Pricing Game

In this game Ashok’s is at the first decision node so they get to move first. Tridip’s is at the second set of decision nodes so they move second. How will the game resolve itself? To determine the outcome it is necessary to use backward induction: to start at the last play of the game and determine what the player with the last turn of the game will do in each situation and then, given this deduction, determine what the payer with the second to last turn will do at that turn, and continue this way until the first turn is reached. Using backward induction leads to the Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium of the game. The Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium (SPNE) is the solution in which every player, at every turn of the game, is playing an individually optimal strategy.

For the curry pricing game illustrated in Figure 18.3.1, the SPNE is found by first determining what Tridip will do for each possible play by Ashok. Tridip is only concerned with his payoffs in red and will play Medium if Ashok plays High and get 410, will play Low if Ashok plays Medium and get 360, and will play Low if Ashok plays Low and get 310. Because of common knowledge, Ashok knows this as well and so has only three possible outcomes. Ashok knows that if he plays High, Tridip will play Medium and he will get 340; if he plays Medium, Tridip will play Low and he will get 210, and if he plays Low, Tridip will play Low and he will get 320. Since 340 is best of the possible outcomes, Ashok will pick High. Since Ashok picks high, Tridip will pick Medium and the game ends.

Backward induction will always lead to the SPNE of a sequential game.

Credible and Non-Credible Threats

Let’s consider a famous game where there is an established ‘incumbent’ firm in a market and another entrepreneur who is thinking of entering the market and competing with the incumbent who we will call the ‘potential entrant.’ Suppose, for example, that there is just one pizza restaurant in a commercial district just off a university campus that sells pizza slices to the students of the university, let’s call it Gino’s. Since they face no direct competition, they can sell a slice of pizza for $3 and they make $400 a day in revenue. But there is a pizza maker named Vito who is considering entering the market by setting up a pizza shop in an empty storefront just down the street from Gino’s. When facing the potential arrival of Vito’s pizza restaurant, Gino has two choices: accommodate Vito by keeping prices higher (say $2) or fighting Vito by selling his slices below cost in the hope of preventing Vito from opening. The game and the payoffs are given below in the normal form game in figure 18.3.2.

Figure 18.3.2: The Market Entry Game

Vito’s (Potential Entrant)

Enter

Don’t Enter

Gino’s

(Incumbent)

Accommodate

200, 300

400, 0

Fight

100, 200

400, 0

If we follow the underlining strategy to identify best responses we see that this game has two Nash Equilibria: (Accommodate, Enter) and (Fight, Don’t Enter). Note that for Gino, both Accommodate and Fight result in the same payoff if Vito chooses don’t enter, so we underline both – either one is equally a best response.

Vito’s (Potential Entrant)

Enter

Don’t Enter

Gino’s

(Incumbent)

Accommodate

200, 300

400, 0

Fight

-100, -100

400, 0

But there is something unsatisfying about the second Nash equilibrium – since this is a simultaneous game both player are picking their strategies simultaneously, thus Gino is picking fight if Vito does not enter and so Vito’s best choice is not to enter. But would Vito really believe that Gino would fight if he entered? Probably not. We call this a non-credible threat: a strategy choice to dissuade a rival that is against the best interest of the player and therefore not rational.

A better description of this game is therefore a sequential one, where Vito first chooses to open a pizza restaurant and Gino has to decide how to respond.

Figure 18.3.3: The Sequential Market Entry Game

In this version of the game, if Vito decides not to enter the game ends and the payoffs are $0 for Vito and $400 for Gino. If Vito decides to enter then Gino can either fight and get $-100, or accommodate and get $200. Clearly the only individually rational thing for Gino to do if Vito enters is to accommodate and, since Vito knows this he will enter.

The SPNE of this game is (Enter, Accommodate). What this version of the game does is to eliminate the equilibrium based on a non-credible threat. Vito knows that if he decides to open up a pizza shop, it is irrational for Gino to fight because Gino will make himself worse off. Since Vito knows that Gino will accommodate, the best decision for Vito is to open his restaurant.

18.4 Repeated Games

Learning Objective 18.4: Describe repeated games and the difference between finitely repeated game and infinitely repeated games and their equilibrium.

Any game can be played more than once to create a larger game. For example, the game “rock, scissors, paper” where two players simultaneously use their hands to form the shape of a rock or a piece of paper or scissors can be played just once, or can be repeated multiple times for example playing “best of 3” where the winner is the first player to win two rounds of the game. This is a normal form game in each round but a larger game when taken as a whole. This raises the possibility that a larger strategy could be employed, for example one contingent on the strategy choice of the opponent in the last round.

Let’s return to the Valedictorian game from section 18.2. Recall that this game was a prisoner’s dilemma, because of individual incentives they find themselves in a collectively suboptimal outcome. In other words there is an outcome that they both prefer but they fail to reach it because of the individual strategic incentive to try and do better for themselves. But if the same game was repeated more than once over the course of the school year it is quite reasonable to ask if such repetition would lead the players to a different outcome. If the players know they will face the same situation again, will they be more inclined to cooperate and reach the mutually beneficial outcome?

Finitely Repeated Games

If we played the valedictorian game twice, then the strategies for each player would entail their strategy choices for each round of the game. In other words a ‘strategy’ for a repeated game is the complete set of strategic choices for every round of the game. So let’s ask if playing the Valedictorian game twice would alter the outcome in an individual round. Suppose, for example, the two talked before the game and acknowledged that they would both be better off cooperating and sharing. In the repeated game, is cooperation ever a Nash equilibrium strategy?

To answer this question we have to think about how to solve the game. Since this game is repeated a finite number of times, in our case two, it has a last round and similar to a sequential game, the appropriate method of solving the game is through backward induction to find the Subgame Perfect Nash Equilibrium. In repeated games at each round the subsequent games are a subgame of the overall game. So in our case the second and final round of the game is a subgame. So to solve the game we have to first think about the outcome of the final round. Well this final play of the game is the simple normal form game we have already solved, a single-shot, simultaneous play game with one Nash equilibrium: (Don’t Share, Don’t Share).

Figure 18.2.1: The Valedictorian Game

Sven

Share

Don’t Share

Lena

Share

100, 100

90, 110

Don’t Share

110, 90

95, 95

Now that we know what will happen in the final round of the game, we have to ask ourselves, what is the Nash equilibrium strategy in the first round of play. Since they both know that in the final round of play the only outcome is for both to not share, they also know that there is no reason to share in the first round either. Why? Well, even if they agree to share, when push comes to shove, not sharing is better individually, and since not sharing is going to happen in the final round anyway, there is no way to create an incentive to share in the first round through a final round punishment mechanism. In essence, after the last period is revealed to be a single-shot prisoner’s dilemma game, the second to last period becomes a single-shot prisoner’s dilemma game as well because there is nothing in the last round that can alter the incentives in the second to last round, so the game is identical.

In fact, as long as there is a final round, it doesn’t matter how many times we repeat this game, because of backward induction, it simply becomes a series of single-shot games with the Nash equilibrium strategies being played every time.

Infinitely Repeated Games

Things change when normal-form games are repeated infinitely because there is no final round and thus backward induction does not work, there is no where to work backward from. This aspect of the games allows space for reward and punishment strategies that might create incentives under which cooperation becomes a Nash Equilibrium.

To see this let’s alter the scenario of our Valedictorian game. Suppose that Lena and Sven are now adults in the workplace and they work together in a company where their pay is based partly on their performance on a monthly aptitude test. For simplicity we’ll assume that their payoffs are the same as in the Valedictorian game but, this time that represent cash bonuses. The key here is that they foresee working together for as long as they can imagine. In other words they each perceive the possibility that they will keep playing this game for in indeterminate amount of time – there is no determined last round of the game and therefore no way to use backward induction to solve it. Player have to look forward to determine optimal strategies.

So would could a strategy to induce cooperation look like? Suppose Lena says to Sven I will share with you as long as you share with me, but as soon as you don’t share, I will stop sharing with you forever – let’s call this the ‘cooperate’ strategy. Sven, in response says, okay, I will do the same, I will share with you until such time as you don’t share and then I’ll stop sharing together. The question we have to answer is: is both players playing these strategies a Nash equilibrium?

To answer this question we have to figure out the best response to the strategy, is it to play the same strategy or is there a better strategy to play in response? To determine the answer to this question let’s think about playing the same strategy and alternate strategies and their payoffs.

If Lena claims she will play the cooperate strategy, what is Sven’s outcome if he plays the cooperate strategy in response? Well, in the first period Sven will get 100 because they both share and since they both shared in period one they will both share in period two, Sven will get 100 and it will continue on like this forever. To put a present day value on future earnings, we discount, so Sven’s earnings stream looks like this:

Payoff from cooperate strategy:

100+100×d+100×d2+100×d3+100×d4+…

What is the payoff from not cooperating? Well in the period in which Sven decides not to share, Lena will still be sharing and so Sven will get 110 but then after that Lena will not share and Sven knows this so he will not share as well and he will therefore get 95 for every round after. Let’s call this strategy ‘deviate.’ Thus his earning stream looks like this:

Payoff from deviate strategy:

110+95×d+95×d2+95×d3+95×d4+…

Note that we are only comparing the two strategies from the moment Sven decides to deviate, as the two payoff steams are identical up to that point and therefore cancel themselves out.

Is to cooperate the best response to the cooperate strategy? Yes, if:

100+100×d+100×d2+100×d3+100×d4+…

>110+95×d+95×d2+95×d3+95×d4+…

Rearranging:

5 (d+d2+d3+d4+…) > 10

This says that cooperation is better as long as the extra 5 a cooperating player gets for every subsequent period after the first is better than the extra 10 the deviating player gets in the first period. To determine if this is true, we have to use the result that

d+d2+d3+d4+… = [latex]\frac{d}{1-4}[/latex]

So: [latex]5(\frac{d}{1-d})>10[/latex]

or

5d > 10(1-d)

15d > 10

d > [latex]\frac{2}{3}[/latex]

You can think of d as a measure of how much the players care about future payoffs, and so this says that as long as they care enough about the future payoffs, they will cooperate. In other words if d> [latex]\frac{2}{3}[/latex] , then playing cooperate is a best response to the other player playing cooperate and vice-versa: the strategy pair (cooperate, cooperate) is a Nash equilibrium for the infinitely repeated game.

This type of strategy has a name in economics, it is called a trigger strategy. A trigger strategy is one where cooperative play continues until an opponent deviates and then ceases permanently or for a specified number of periods. An alternate strategy is the tit-for-tat strategy where a player simply plays the same strategy their opponent played in the previous round. Tit-for-tat strategies can also be Nash equilibrium and, in fact, in infinitely repeated games there are often many Nash equilibria, the trigger strategy identified above is but one.

 

SUMMARY

Review: Topics and Related Learning Outcomes

18.1 What is Game Theory?

Learning Objective 18.1: Describe game theory and they types of situations it describes.

18.2 Single Play Games

Learning Objective 18.2: Describe normal form games and identify optimal strategies and equilibrium outcomes in such games.

18.3 Sequential Games

Learning Objective 18.3: Describe sequential move games and explain how they are solved.

18.4 Repeated Games

Learning Objective 18.4: Describe repeated games and the difference between finitely repeated game and infinitely repeated games and their equilibrium.

Learn: Key Terms and Graphs

Terms

Strategic interactions

Game theory

Non-cooperative games

Players

Strategies

Payoffs

Simultaneous games

Sequential games

Single-shot games

Repeated games

Common knowledge

Payoff matrix

Normal-form games

Dominant strategy

Dominated strategy

Dominant strategy equilibrium (dse)

Best response function

Nash equilibrium

Pure strategies

Mixed strategies

Sequential move games

Game tree

Extensive form games.

Subgame perfect Nash equilibrium (spne)

Trigger strategy

Tit-for-tat strategy

Graphs

The Valedictorian Game

The Party Game

The Party Game, Version 2

The Matching Pennies Game

The Curry Pricing Game

The Market Entry Game

The Sequential Market Entry Game

Supplemental Resources

YouTube Videos

There are no supplemental YouTube videos for this module.

There are no supplemental reading materials for this module.

Policy Example

Policy Example: Do We Need to Regulate Banks to Save Them From Themselves?

Learning Objective: Explain how game theory can be used to understand the banking collapse of 2008.

In the mid two thousands banks in the United States found themselves struggling to satisfy a tremendous demand for mortgages from the market for mortgage back securities: securities that were created from bundles of residential or commercial mortgages. This, along with the low-interest rate policy of the Federal Reserve, led to a tremendous housing boom in the United States that evolved into a speculative investment bubble. The bursting of this bubble led to the housing market crash and, in 2008, to a banking crisis: the failure of major banking institutions and the unprecedented government bailout of banks. These twin crises led to the worst recession since the great depression.

Interestingly, this banking crisis came relatively soon after a series of reforms of banking regulations in the United States that gave banks much more freedom in their operations. Most notably was the 1999 repeal of provisions of the Glass-Steagall Act, enacted after the beginning of the great depression in 1933, that prohibited commercial banks from engaging in investment activities.

Part of the argument of the time of the repeal was that banks should be allowed to innovate and be more flexible which would benefit consumers. The rationale was increased competition and the discipline of the market would inhibit excessive risk-taking and so stringent government regulation was no longer necessary. But the discipline of the market assumes that rewards are absolute that returns are not based on relative performance that the environment is not strategic. Is this an accurate description of modern banking? Probably not.

In everything from stock prices to CEO pay relative performance matters, and if one bank were to rely on a low-risk strategy whilst others were engaging in higher risk-higher reward strategies both the company’s stock price and the compensation of the CEO might suffer. We can describe this in a very simplified model where there are two banks and they can either engage in low risk or high-risk strategies. This scenario is described in Figure 1 where we have two players, Big Bank and Huge Bank, the two strategies for each and the payoffs (in Millions):

Figure 1: The Risky Banking Game

Huge Bank

Low-Risk

High-Risk

Big Bank

Low-Risk

30, 30

22, 45

High-Risk

45, 22

25, 25

We can see from the normal form game that the banks both have dominant strategies: High Risk. This is because the rewards are relative. Being a high-risk bank when your competitor is a low-risk bank brings a big reward; the relatively high returns are compounded by the reward from the stock market. In the end, both banks end up choosing high-risk and are in a worse outcome than if they had chosen a low risk strategy because of the increased likelihood of negative events from the strategy. Astute observers will recognize this game as a prisoner’s dilemma where behavior based on the individual self-interest of the banks leads them to a second-best outcome. If you include the cost to society of bailing out high-risk banks when they fail, the second-best outcome is that much worse.

Can policy correct the situation and lead to a mutually beneficial outcome? The answer in this case is a resounding ‘yes.’ If policy makers take away the ability of the banks to engage in high-risk strategies, the bad equilibrium will disappear and only the low-risk, low-risk outcome will remain. The banks are better off and because the adverse effects of high-risk strategies going bad are taken away, society benefits as well.

Exploring the Policy Question

  1. Why do you think that banks were so willing to engage in risky bets in the early 2000nds?
  2. Do you think that government regulation restricting their strategy choices is appropriate in cases where society has to pay for risky bets gone bad?

 

definition

License

Icon for the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License

Module 18: Game Theory Copyright © by Joel Bruneau and Clinton Mahoney is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book